Bachelor thesis about the Dold-Kan correspondence https://github.com/Jaxan/Dold-Kan
You can not select more than 25 topics Topics must start with a letter or number, can include dashes ('-') and can be up to 35 characters long.
This repo is archived. You can view files and clone it, but cannot push or open issues/pull-requests.
 
 

262 lines
19 KiB

\section{The Dold-Kan correspondence}
\label{sec:Constructions}
Comparing chain complexes and simplicial abelian groups, one sees a certain similarity. Both concepts are defined as sequences of abelian groups with certain structure maps. At first sight simplicial abelian groups seem to have a richer structure. There are many face maps as opposed to only a single boundary homomorphism. Nevertheless, as we will show in this section, these two concepts give rise to equivalent categories.
\subsection{Unnormalized chain complex}
Given a simplicial abelian group $A$, we have a family of abelian groups $A_n$. For every $n>0$ we define a group homomorphism
$$\del_n = d_0 - d_1 + \ldots + (-1)^n d_n: A_n \to A_{n-1}.$$
\begin{lemma}
Using $A_n$ as the family of abelian groups and the maps $\del_n$ as boundary maps gives a chain complex.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
We already have a collection of abelian groups together with maps, so the only thing to prove is $\del_{n-1} \circ \del_n = 0$. This can be done with a calculation.
\begin{align*}
\del_{n-1} \circ \del_n &= \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=0}^{n} (-1)^{i+j} d_i \circ d_j \\
&\eqn{1} \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=0}^{i} (-1)^{i+j} d_i \circ d_j + \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=i+1}^{n} (-1)^{i+j} d_i \circ d_j \\
&\eqn{2} \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=0}^{i} (-1)^{i+j} d_i \circ d_j + \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=i+1}^{n} (-1)^{i+j} d_{j-1} \circ d_i \\
&\eqn{3} \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=0}^{i} (-1)^{i+j} d_i \circ d_j - \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=i}^{n-1} (-1)^{i+j} d_j \circ d_i \\
&= \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=0}^{i} (-1)^{i+j} d_i \circ d_j - \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} \sum_{j=0}^{i} (-1)^{i+j} d_i \circ d_j = 0
\end{align*}
In this calculation we did the following. We split the inner sum in two halves \refeqn{1} and we use the simplicial equations on the second sum \refeqn{2}. Then we do a shift of indices \refeqn{3}. By interchanging the roles of $i$ and $j$ in the second sum, we have two equal sums which cancel out. So indeed this is a chain complex.
\end{proof}
Thus, associated to a simplicial abelian group $A$ we obtain a chain complex $M(A)$ with $M(A)_n = A_n$ and the boundary operator as above. Following the book \cite{goerss} we will call the chain complex $M(X)$ the \emph{Moore complex} or \emph{unnormalized chain complex} of $X$. This construction defines a functor
$$ M: \sAb \to \Ch{\Ab} $$
by assigning $M(f)_n = f_n$ for a natural transformation $f: A \to B$. It follows from a nice calculation that $M(f)$ is indeed a chain map:
\begin{align*}
f_{n-1} \circ \del &= f_{n-1} \circ (d_0 - d_1 + \ldots + (-1)^n d_n) \\
&= f_{n-1} \circ d_0 - f_{n-1} \circ d_1 + \ldots + (-1)^n f_{n-1} \circ d_n \\
&\eqn{1} d_0 \circ f_n - d_1 \circ f_n + \ldots + (-1)^n d_n \circ f_n \\
&= (d_0 - d_1 + \ldots + (-1)^n d_n) \circ f_n = \del \circ f_n,
\end{align*}
where we used naturality of $f$ in step \refeqn{1}. This functor is in fact already used in the construction of the singular chain complex, where we defined the boundary maps (on generators) as $\del(\sigma) = \sigma \circ d_0 - \sigma \circ d_1 + \ldots + (-1)^{n+1} \sigma \circ d_{n+1}$. We will briefly come back to this in Section~\ref{sec:Homotopy}.
Let us investigate whether this functor $M$ can be part of an equivalence. For a functor from $\Ch{\Ab}$ to $\sAb$ we cannot simply take the same collection of abelian groups. This is due to the fact that the degeneracy maps should be injective. This means that for a simplicial abelian group $A$, if we know $A_n$ is non-trivial, then all $A_m$ for $m > n$ are also non-trivial.
But for chain complexes it \emph{is} possible to have trivial abelian groups $C_m$, while there is a $n < m$ with $C_n$ non-trivial. Take for example the chain complex
$$ C = \ldots \to 0 \to 0 \to \Z. $$
Now if we would construct a (non-trivial) simplicial abelian group $K(C)$ from this chain complex, we now know that $K(C)_n$ is non-trivial for all $n \in \N$. This means that $M(K(C))_n$ is non-trivial for all $n \in \N$. For an equivalence we require a (natural) isomorphism: $M(K(C)) \tot{\iso} C$, this in particular means an isomorphism in each degree $n > 0$: $ 0 \neq M(K(C))_n \tot{\iso} C_n = 0 $, which is not possible. So the functor $M$, as defined as above, will not give us the equivalence we wanted, although it is a very nice functor.
\subsection{Normalized chain complex}
To repair this defect we should be more careful. Given a simplicial abelian group, simply taking the same collection for our chain complex will not work (as shown above). Instead we are after some ``smaller'' abelian groups, and in some cases the abelian groups should completely vanish (as in the example above).
Given a simplicial abelian group $A$, we define abelian groups $N(A)_n$ as
\begin{align*}
N(A)_n &= \bigcap_{i=1}^{n} \ker(d_i: A_n \to A_{n-1}), \quad\text{n > 0} \\
N(A)_0 &= A_0.
\end{align*}
Now define group homomorphisms $\del: N(A)_n \to N(A)_{n-1}$ as
$$ \del = d_0|_{N(A)_n}. $$
\begin{lemma}
The function $ \del $ is well-defined. Furthermore $ \del \circ \del = 0 $.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Let $x \in N(A)_n$, then $d_i \del(x) = d_i d_0(x) = d_0 d_{i+1}(x) = d_0 (0) = 0$ for all $i < n$. So indeed $\del(x) \in N(A)_{n-1}$, because in particular it holds for $i > 0$. Using this calculation for $i = 0$ shows that $\del \circ \del = 0$. This shows that $N(A)$ is a chain complex.
\end{proof}
The chain complex $N(A)$ is called the \emph{normalized chain complex} of $A$.
\begin{lemma}
The above construction gives a functor $N: \sAb \to \Ch{\Ab}$. Furthermore $N$ is additive.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Given a map $f: A \to B$ of simplicial abelian groups, we consider the restrictions
$$ f_n |_{N(A)_n}: N(A)_n \to B_n. $$
Because $f_n$ commutes with the face maps we get
$$ d_i(f_n(x)) = f_{n-1}(d_i(x)) = 0, $$
for $i>0$ and $x \in N(A)_n$. So the restriction also restricts the codomain, i.e. $f_n |_{N(A)_n}: N(A)_n \to N(B)_n$ is well-defined. Furthermore it commutes with the boundary operator, since $f$ itself commutes with all face maps. This gives functoriality $N(f): N(A) \to N(B)$.
Let $f, g: A \to B$ be two maps, then
$$ N(f+g) = (f+g)|_{N(A)} = f|_{N(A)} + g|_{N(A)} = N(f) + N(g). $$
By recalling that in both categories addition of maps was defined pointwise, we have additivity of $N$.
\end{proof}
\begin{example}
We will look at the normalized chain complex of $\Z[\Delta[0]]$. Recall that it looks like
$$ \Z[\Delta[0]] :=
\begin{tikzpicture}[baseline=-0.5ex]
\matrix (m) [matrix of math nodes] {
\Z & \Z & \Z & \cdots \\
};
\foreach \r in {-5, 5} \draw [raise line=\r, <-] (m-1-1) -> (m-1-2);
\foreach \r in {0} \draw [raise line=\r, ->] (m-1-1) -> (m-1-2);
\foreach \r in {-10, 0, 10} \draw [raise line=\r, <-] (m-1-2) -> (m-1-3);
\foreach \r in {-5, 5} \draw [raise line=\r, ->] (m-1-2) -> (m-1-3);
\foreach \r in {-15, -5, 5, 15} \draw [raise line=\r, <-] (m-1-3) -> (m-1-4);
\foreach \r in {-10, 0, 10} \draw [raise line=\r, ->] (m-1-3) -> (m-1-4);
\end{tikzpicture}.$$
where all face and degeneracy maps are identity maps. Clearly the kernel of $\id$ is the trivial group. So $N(\Z[\Delta[0]])_i = 0$ for all $i > 0$. In degree zero we are left with $N(\Z[\Delta[0]])_0 = \Z$. So we can depict the normalized chain complex by
$$ N(\Z[\Delta[0]]) = \cdots \to 0 \to 0 \to \Z. $$
So in this example we see that the normalized chain complex is really better behaved than the unnormalized chain complex given by $M(\Z[\Delta[0]]$.
\end{example}
To see what $N$ exactly does there are some useful lemmas. These lemmas can also be found in \cite[Chapter~VIII~1-2]{lamotke}, but in this thesis more detail is provided. Some corollaries are provided to give some intuition, or so summarize the lemmas, these results can also be found in \cite[Chapter~8.2-4]{weibel}. For the following lemmas let $X \in \sAb$ be an arbitrary simplicial abelian group and $n \in \N$. For these lemmas we will need the subgroups $D_n(X) \subset X_n$ of degenerate simplices, defined as:
$$ D_n(X) = \sum_{i=0}^n s_i(X_{n-1}). $$
\begin{lemma}
\label{le:decomp1}
For all $x \in X_n$ we have:
$$ x = b + c,$$
where $b \in N(X)_n$ and $c \in D_n(X)$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Define the subgroup $P_n^k = \{ x \in X_n \I d_i x = 0 \text{ for all } i > k\}$. Note that by definition we have
$$ N(X)_n = P_n^0 \subseteq P_n^1 \subseteq \ldots \subseteq P_n^{n-1} \subseteq P_n^n = X_n. $$
We will prove with induction that for any $k \leq n$ we can write $x \in X_n$ as $x = b + c$, with $b \in P_n^k$ and $c \in D_n(X)$. For $k = n$ the statement is clear, because we can simply write $x = x$, knowing that $x \in P_n^n = X_n$.
Assume the statement holds for $k > 0$, we will prove it for $k-1$. So for any $x \in X_n$ we have $x = b + c$, with $b \in P_n^k$ and $c \in D_n(X)$. Now consider $b' = b - s_{k-1} d_k b$. Now clearly for all $i > k$ we have $d_i b' = 0$. For $k$ itself we can calculate
$$ d_k(b') = d_k(b - s_{k-1} d_k b) = d_k b - d_k s_{k-1} d_k b = d_k b - d_k b = 0, $$
where we used the equality $d_k s_{k-1} = \id$. So $b' \in P_n^{k-1}$. Furthermore we can define $c' = s_{k-1} d_k b + c$, for which it is clear that $c' \in D_n(X)$. Finally conclude that
$$ x = b + c = b - s_{k-1} d_k b + s_{k-1} d_k b + c = b' + c',$$
with $b' \in P_n^{k-1}$ and $c' \in D_n(X)$.
Doing this inductively gives us $x = b + c$, with $b \in P_n^0 = N(X)_n$ and $c \in D_n(X)$, which is what we had to prove.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{le:decomp2}
For all $x \in X_n$, if $s_i x \in N(X)_{n+1}$, then $x = 0$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Using that $s_i x \in N(X)_{n+1}$ means $0 = d_{k+1} s_i x$ for any $k \geq 0$ and by using using the simplicial identity: $d_{i+1} s_i = \id$, we can conclude $x = d_{i+1} s_i x = 0$.
\end{proof}
The first lemma tells us that every $n$-simplex in $X$ can be decomposed as a sum of something in $N(X)$ and a degenerate $n$-simplex. The latter lemma assures that there are no degenerate $n$-simplices in $N(X)$. So this gives us:
\begin{corollary}
\label{cor:NandD}
$X_n = N(X)_n \oplus D_n(X)$
\end{corollary}
We can extend the above lemmas to a more general statement.
\begin{lemma}
\label{le:decomp3}
For all $x \in X_n$ we can write $x$ as
$$ x = \sum_\beta \beta^\ast (x_\beta), $$
for certain $x_\beta \in N(X)_p$, where $\beta$ ranges over all surjective functions $\beta : [n] \epi [p]$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
We will proof this using induction on $n$. For $n=0$ the statement is clear because $N(X)_0 = X_0$.
Assume the statement is proven for $n$. Let $x \in X_{n+1}$, then from Lemma~\ref{le:decomp1} we see $x = b + c$. Note that $c \in D_n(X)$, in other words $c = \sum_{i=0}^{n-1} s_i c_i$, with $c_i \in X_n$. So with the induction hypothesis, we can write these as $c_i = \sum_\beta \beta^\ast c_{i, \beta}$, where the sum quantifies over $\beta: [n] \epi [p]$. Now $b$ is already in $N(X)_{n+1}$, so we can set $x_\id = b$, to obtain the conclusion.
\end{proof}
\begin{lemma}
\label{le:decomp4}
Let $\beta: [n] \epi [m]$ and $\gamma : [n] \epi [m']$ be two maps such that $\beta \neq \gamma$. Then we have $\beta^\ast(N(X))_m \cap \gamma^\ast(N(X))_{m'} = 0$.
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
Note that $N(X)_i$ only contains non-degenerate $i$-simplices (and $0$). For $x \in \beta^\ast(N(X))_p \cap \gamma^\ast(N(X))_q$ we have $x = \beta^\ast y = \gamma^\ast y'$, where $y$ and $y'$ are non-degenerate. By Lemma~\ref{le:non-degenerate} we know that every $n$-simplex is \emph{uniquely} determined by a non-degenerate simplex and a surjective map. For $x \neq 0$ this gives a contradiction.
\end{proof}
Again the former lemma of these two lemmas proves the existence of a decomposition and the latter shows the uniqueness. So combining these gives:
\begin{corollary}
\label{cor:decomp}
For all $x \in X_n$ we can write $x = \sum_\beta \beta^\ast (x_\beta)$ in a unique way.
\end{corollary}
And by considering $X_n$ as a whole we get:
\begin{corollary}
$X_n = \bigoplus_{[n] \epi [p]} N(X)_p$.
\end{corollary}
Using Corollary~\ref{cor:decomp} we can prove a nice categorical fact about $N$, which we will use later on.
\begin{lemma}
The functor $N$ is fully faithful, i.e.
$$ N: \Hom{\sAb}{A}{B} \iso \Hom{\Ch{\Ab}}{N(A)}{N(B)} \quad A, B \in \sAb. $$
\end{lemma}
\begin{proof}
First we prove that $N$ is injective on maps. Let $f: A \to B$ and assume $N(f) = 0$, for $x \in A_n$ we know $x = \sum_\beta \beta^\ast x_\beta$, so
\begin{align*}
f(x) &= \textstyle f(\sum_\beta \beta^\ast (x_\beta)) \\
&= \textstyle \sum_\beta f(\beta^\ast (x_\beta)) \\
&= \textstyle \sum_\beta \beta^\ast (f (x_\beta)) \\
&= \textstyle \sum_\beta \beta^\ast (N(f) (x_\beta)) = 0,
\end{align*}
where we used naturality of $f$ in the second step, and the fact that $x_\beta \in N(A)$ in the last step. We now see that $f(x) = 0$ for all $x$, hence $f = 0$. So indeed $N$ is injective on maps.
Secondly we have to prove $N$ is surjective on maps. Let $g: N(A) \to N(B)$, define $f: A \to B$ as
$$ f(x) = \sum_\beta \beta^\ast g(x_\beta), $$
again we have written $x$ as $x = \sum_\beta \beta^\ast x_\beta$. Clearly $N(f) = g$.
\end{proof}
If we reflect a bit on why the functor $M$ was not a candidate for an equivalence, we see that $N$ does a better job. We see that $N$ leaves out all degenerate simplices, so it is more carefully chosen than $M$, which included everything. In fact, Corollary~\ref{cor:NandD} exactly tells us $M(X)_n = N(X)_n \oplus D_n(X)$.
\subsection{From $\Ch{\Ab}$ to $\sAb$}
\begin{definition}
For a chain complex $C$ define the abelian groups
$$ K(C)_n = \bigoplus_{\beta} C_p^\beta, $$
where $\beta$ ranges over all surjections $\beta: [n] \epi [p]$ and $C_p^\beta = C_p$ ($\beta$ only acts as a decoration).
\end{definition}
For a chain complex $C$ we will turn the groups $K(C)_n$ into a simplicial abelian group by defining $K$ on functions. Let $\alpha: [m] \to [n]$ be a function in $\DELTA$, we will define $K(\alpha): K(C)_n \to K(C)_m$ by defining it on each summand $C_p^\beta$. Fix a summand $C_p^\beta$, by using the epi-mono factorization we know $\beta\alpha = \delta\sigma$ for some injection $\delta$ and some surjection $\sigma$. In the case $\delta = \id$, we make the following identification
$$ C_p^\beta \tot{=} C_p^\sigma \subset K(C)_m. $$
In the case $\delta = \delta_0$ we use the boundary operator as follows:
$$ C_p^\beta \tot{\del} C_{p-1} \tot{=} C_{p-1}^\sigma \subseteq K(C)_m. $$
In all the other cases we define the map $C_p^\beta \to K(C)_m$ to be the zero map. We now have defined a map on each of the summands which gives a map $K(\alpha): K(C)_n \to K(C)_m$.
\todo{DK: functoriality of $K(C)$, functoriality of $K$}
\todo{DK: work out the following in more detail (especially the naturalities)}
\begin{theorem}
$N$ and $K$ form an equivalence.
\end{theorem}
\begin{proof}
Let $X$ be a simplicial abelian group. Consider $X_n$, by the additive Yoneda lemma this is naturally isomorphic to $\Z^\ast[\Delta[n]] \to X$, which is by the fully faithfulness and additivity of $N$ naturally isomorphic to $N\Z^\ast[\Delta[n]] \to NX$. The latter is exactly the definition of $KNX$. So, by naturality in $n$, we have established $X \iso KNX$. Hence, by naturality in $X$, we have $\id \iso KN$.
By the previous proposition we have $K(C)_n \iso \bigoplus_{[n] \epi [p]} C_p$. For the summands $C_p$ with $p < n$, we clearly see that $C_p \subset D_n(K(C))$, so $N$ gets rid of these. Then the only summand left is $C_n$ (with the surjection $\id : [n] \epi [n]$). So we see $NKC_n \iso C_n$, furthermore the boundary map is preserved. Hence $NKC \iso C$. And this was natural in $C$, so we get $NK \iso \id$.
We now have established two natural isomorphisms $\id_\sAb \iso KN$ and $NK \iso \id_\Ch{\Ab}$. Hence we have an equivalence $\Ch{\Ab} \simeq \sAb$.
\end{proof}
One might not be content with the explicit description of the functor $K$. There is a more abstract way of constructing a functor $\Ch{\Ab} \to \sAb$ from a functor $\sAb \to \Ch{\Ab}$. We will briefly discuss this and show how the functor $K$ would be derived from $N$ by this abstract construction, with two examples it will be illustrated why the two descriptions are the same.
Let $A$ be an additive category and $F: \sAb \to A$ an additive functor. We want to construct a functor $G: A \to \sAb$ which is right adjoint to $F$. For each $a \in A$ we have to specify $G(a): \DELTA^{op} \to \Ab$. Assume we already specified this, such that $G$ is the right adjoint, then by the additive Yoneda lemma we know
\begin{align*}
G(a)_n &\iso \Hom{\sAb}{\Z[\Delta[n]]}{G(a)} \\
&\iso \Hom{A}{F\Z[\Delta[n]]}{a}.
\end{align*}
This in fact can be used as the definition of $G$:
$$ G(a)_n = \Hom{A}{F\Z[\Delta[n]]}{a}. $$
To check that indeed $G(a) \in \sAb$ we only have to remind ourselves that we only composed two functors, namely
\begin{gather*}
\DELTA \tot{\Delta[-]} \sSet \tot{\Z} \sAb \tot{F} A \quad\text{and} \\
\Hom{A}{-}{a}: A^{op} \to \Ab
\end{gather*}
giving us $\Hom{A}{F\Z[\Delta[-]]}{a}: \DELTA^{op} \to \Ab$. Similarly $G$ itself is a functor, because it is defined using the $\mathbf{Hom}$-functor.
Many functors to $\sAb$ can be shown to have this description.\footnote{And also many functors to $\sSet$ are of this form if we leave out all additivity requirements.} In our case we could have defined our functor $K$ as
$$ K'(C) = \Hom{\Ch{\Ab}}{N\Z[\Delta[-]]}{C}. $$
We will not show that this functor $K'$ is isomorphic to our functor $K$ defined earlier, however we will indicate that it makes sense by writing out explicit calculations for $K'(C)_0$ and $K'(C)_1$. First we see that
$$ K'(C)_0 = \Hom{\Ch{\Ab}}{N\Z^\ast\Delta[0]}{C} = \Bigg\{
\begin{tikzpicture}[baseline=-0.5ex]
\matrix (m) [matrix of math nodes, row sep=1em, column sep=1em] {
\cdots & 0 & 0 & \Z \\
\cdots & C_2 & C_1 & C_0 \\
};
\foreach \x in {1, 2}
\foreach \i/\j in {1/2, 2/3, 3/4} \draw[->] (m-\x-\i) -- (m-\x-\j);
\foreach \i/\j in {2/2, 3/1, 4/0} \draw[->] (m-1-\i) -- node {$f_\j$} (m-2-\i);
\end{tikzpicture}
\Bigg\} \iso C_0 = K(C)_0, $$
because for $f_1, f_2, \ldots$ there is now choice at all, and for $f_0: \Z \to C_0$ we only have to choose an image for $1 \in \Z$. In the next dimension we see
$$ K'(C)_1 = \Hom{\Ch{\Ab}}{N\Z^\ast\Delta[1]}{C} = \Bigg\{
\begin{tikzpicture}[baseline=-0.5ex]
\matrix (m) [matrix of math nodes, row sep=1em, column sep=1em] {
\cdots & 0 & \Z & \Z^2 \\
\cdots & C_2 & C_1 & C_0 \\
};
\foreach \x in {1, 2}
\foreach \i/\j in {1/2, 2/3, 3/4} \draw[->] (m-\x-\i) -- (m-\x-\j);
\foreach \i/\j in {2/2, 3/1, 4/0} \draw[->] (m-1-\i) -- node {$f_\j$} (m-2-\i);
\end{tikzpicture}
\Bigg\} \iso C_1 \oplus C_0 = K(C)_1, $$
because again we can choose $f_1$ anyway we want, which gives us $C_1$. But then we are forced to choose $f_0(x, x) = \del(f_1(x))$ for all $x \in \Z$, so we are left with choosing an element $c \in C_0$ for defining $f(1,-1) = c$. Adding this gives $C_1 \oplus C_0$.